What is the rule of law? In my opinion, it does not exist.
It simply cannot exist. There are too many contradictions, too many gaps, and
too many criteria that even the most utopian society could not declare itself
subject to the rule of law. But to disregard it, we must first understand what
it claims to be.
Nick Barber wrote that the rule of law “asks what it means to be governed by law, rather than men.” The first societies decided their own unofficial laws based on the ideas of their leaders, whereas the first civilisations decided their laws based on the ideas of their people, with the advent of agriculture 10,000 years ago. For a period of about 2 million years, hominid groups (primarily hunter-gatherers) appeared to have distributed justice based on the views of a council of elders, or often a simple individual Their laws were likely based on superstition, natural ideas of justice, and the hocus-pocus of the leaders themselves. When civilisations were developed, while brutalisation continued, justice was a broader concept of the people, and eventually not an oligarchy. Instead of individuals handing out justice on their own ideals, such as an execution for doubting the King’s religious beliefs, a lawful society will instead ask judges to interpret written law. Instead of the power of judge, jury, and executioner being in the hands of the monarch, the powers are in the hands of others, who do not use their own ideas, their own beliefs, but the words written in front of them. This is what it means to be governed by law, and not men.
Indeed, a society governed by law will inevitably mean no one
is above the law, as Bracton says: “The King shall not be subject to men, but
to God and the law: since law makes the King.” No matter who writes the law, be
they dictators or legislators, everyone must be subject to the law for a
society to be governed by it. In English law, the Magna Carta and the Bill of
Rights affirmed that the monarchy was subject to the rule of law, because they
forced the monarch to govern through Parliament, rather than through royal
decree. Similarly, the case of Entick v Carrington decided that even the royal
prerogative – those powers exercised by the Prime Minister in the name of the
Crown – are subject to the rule of law.
There are, however, two main ideas interpreting this: the ‘thin’
conception, and the ‘thick’ conception.
The thin conception, espoused primarily by Raz, makes no demand
for the presence of human rights. Among his criteria for a society under the rule
of law are the principles that laws should not change too frequently, the
judiciary should be independent, and the courts should be accessible. Raz says
that we should not confuse the rule of law with things that we would like to
see our governments do. Under Raz’s theory, Nazi Germany was a society governed
by the rule of law. The Reichstag, in passing the Enabling Act, afforded Hitler
numerous extensive powers and permitted the Holocaust, invasions of neighbouring
countries, and the indoctrination of judges, teachers, and civilians. All sane
people undoubtedly agree that Hitler’s policies were, at the very least, not
moral policies, but they were lawful policies. For Raz, that is enough: Nazi
Germany was governed by the rule of law.
The thick conception, proposed by Fuller, Dworkin, and
others, demands the presence of human rights in a lawful society. Fuller, while
setting out very similar criteria to Raz, stated that law does not exist in a
vacuum: it must be moral to be good law. He says the purpose of the law is to serve
justice, provide social order, and allow for human advancement; the law is
inherently moral, and therefore immoral laws are impossible under the rule of
law. Some theorists, such as Barber, go further and require a minimum level of
education or material well-being, so that not only are people governed by moral
law, but they can understand it, and pursue justice under it. Dworkin, widely
regarded as the expert on the matter, argues that judges have a duty to interpret
the law in line with human rights, and so if a law blatantly abuses these human
rights, such a law will be ignored by the courts.
These two theories both agree on two important concepts: for
a law to be regarded as being under the rule of law, it must apply to people
equally, and it must be enforced by the correct authorities.
This is where the theory of the rule of law falls apart.
As Fuller says: law does not exist in a vacuum. We must take
into account the context in which that law is made and applied. British history
is crowded with acts of mass brutality, genocide, and worse. From the religious
persecutions under Henry VIII, Mary I, and Elizabeth I to the creation of concentration
camps under the Marquess of Salisbury, to genocide committed by Winston Churchill
in the British Empire. Our laws have been written and re-written to allow for
these atrocities to go ahead, and those responsible to avoid repercussions. It
was only in 2015 that the government stopped paying slave-owners compensation
for the emancipation of slaves in 1833. Slave-owners were not tried, convicted,
and punished for their abhorrent crimes against humanity, but instead compensated
for their lost property by a legal system who has, undoubtedly, time and time
again reduced minorities to nothing.
Despite the passage of the Equality Act, the Race Relations
Act, the Sex Discrimination Act, and more throughout the 20th and
the 21st centuries, laws still exist on the British statute book
that create and permit glaring inequalities, and more are created in every Parliament.
It is not merely a failure to create new law that pushes such discrimination,
but the absence of concerted efforts to repeal bad law. The Gender Recognition
Act is widely regarded by the transgender community as outdated and ineffective,
and females still cannot be convicted of rape, to give just two examples.
Under the thin conception of the rule of law, these statutes
are permissible. Our government is, according to Raz, operating well within the
confines of civility.
However, law must be applied to everyone equally, and
without the arbitrary exercise of power. It is an undeniable fact that minority
populations, particularly black Britons, are massively overrepresented in
arrest rates and prison populations. These laws are not being enforced equally,
when there is no substantial evidence that black people commit more crimes than
white people. Indeed, a 2005 study by the Home Office found that white people were
more likely to have committed a crime, and a further 2009 study found no racial
factors in the prevalence of criminal acts, anti-social behaviour, or drug
abuse. Black people, and other minority groups, are no more likely to have
committed crimes than white people, but are 10x more likely to be stopped and
searched, 3x more likely to be arrested, and 2x as likely to be denied bail,
all while serving comparatively longer prison sentences than their white
counterparts, and dying in custody at a much higher rate.
The facts, provided by our own government, give us one
important conclusion: the law is not applied to everyone equally, and therefore
the British government is not abiding by the rule of law, but rather
contravening it.
This brings us to the matter of protests. People,
predominantly of colour, but joined by many white individuals too, are
protesting the racial inequalities prevalent in modern British society, namely in
the criminal justice system. Black people are more than twice as likely to die from
police restraint than white people, and this isn’t down to biology: it’s down
to police brutality.
We have already seen how the British legal system was
constructed to oppress minority groups, including people of colour, and how
police forces often arbitrarily mete out justice to these minorities. They do
so both within the confines of the legal system, but also outside. In essence,
they commit murder. For a society to be governed by the rule of law, not only
must the law apply equally to all people, but the powers afforded to the
government must not be exercised arbitrarily.
The judiciary provides a powerful counterbalance to arbitrary
exercise of government power. As was seen in the Miller (No 2) prorogation case
in late 2019, the Supreme Court of the UK is extraordinarily powerful in
preventing the government from abusing its power. But the judiciary has one important
limit: it is a purely reactionary body. Cases have to be brought before the
court in order for the counterbalance to be imposed, and, when groups are
disenfranchised, their ability to bring cases before a judge are severely
hampered. Through the devastating cuts to legal aid, the dearth of wealth in
minority communities, and the victimisation of people of colour, minority
groups are increasingly unable to bring claims against the government, with its
vast resources, and win. Furthermore, the doctrine of standing also prevents
many cases from being brought before the courts by those who might have the
resources, but lack the individual damage. The case of Fleet Street Casuals permitted
any “public-spirited taxpayer” to bring an action to vindicate the rule of law,
but this was promptly narrowed in the Rose Theatre case and the Pergau Dam
case. This means that wealthy minorities cannot bring actions against the
government for crimes committed against poor minorities, thereby depriving a
massive swathe of people of access to justice.
The main concern that is heard when dealing with the current
Black Lives Matter protests in the UK is its inherent illegality when coupled with
the threat of coronavirus. Large gatherings have been banned by the government
to prevent the spread of COVID-19, and a protest is inevitably a large
gathering. However, black people are also 2x more likely to be fined by the
police for violating lockdown rules, when there is no clear difference in the
propensity of different minorities in actually breaking these rules. Once
again, the law is being applied in an unequal way, and the powers are being
exercised arbitrarily to further the racial biases, not of the police officers
themselves, but the institution of the police as a whole. Genuine concerns have
been raised about the risk of protesters transmitting the virus, particularly given
the vulnerability of ethnic minorities to more severe cases, but these concerns
are heavily outweighed by the necessity of the act of protest.
Never once has there been legal change without protest, and
these protests came during immensely challenging periods in our past, from the
English Civil War, which started as a protest against an unruly monarchy, to protests
against the Iraq War.
These protesters are breaking the law by protesting, just as
the white supremacist protesters are doing also, but there is one crucial
difference in how the law must perceive these: the white supremacists are
protected by the law, they are governed by the rule of law, black people are
not. The rule of law in England only applies, through the actions of our
government to the statutes in the book, to white people, as these are the only people
to whom it applies equally and without arbitrary exercise of power. The Black
Lives Matter protesters, through gathering in large numbers to tearing down
statues of slavers, are not operating outside the rule of law, because there
simply is no rule of law that can be applied to them.
By depriving them of recourse to the courts through the
narrow doctrine of standing, the absence of legal aid, and the wider effects of
systemic racism, the United Kingdom has consciously denied the rule of law to
minority groups, black people in particular. Their protests are outside the
letter of the law, but actually are one of the only ways they can receive the protection
of the law. Whilst concerns about COVID outbreaks are valid, the concerns of decades
of systemic disenfranchisement, degradation and abuse is far more deadly, and
has far more legal consequences.
This essay has sought to argue that, not only are the Black Lives Matter protests in London valid, but they are entirely necessary for establishing a rule of law in our country, something we have lived for far too long without.
Click here for the audio version of this blog post
The opinions of this article are solely those of the author and are not intended to provide accurate legal advice for anyone to rely on. While the content is intended to be factually correct, the author does not accept any responsibility or liability arising from the use or misuse of this article or any loss/inconvenience/damage stemming from this. Legal advice should be sought from a qualified professional, not this blog. The opinions represented in this blog are personal and belong solely to the blog owner, and do not represent those of the people, institutions, or organisations that the owner may or may not be associated with in a professional or personal capacity, unless explicitly stated. The views expressed by any podcast guest are their own entirely, and do not necessarily reflect those of the blog owner. The blog owner is not responsible and liable for any discrepancy, if any. Any content provided by this blog or its companion podcast is not intended to malign any religion, ethnic group, club, organisation, company, individual, or anyone or anything.
An intricate history and weaving of examples in an extremely well written essay. Very interesting.
ReplyDeleteThank you so much!
Delete